Social Epistemology - CHSS

Transcription

Social Epistemology - CHSS
This article was downloaded by:[University of Quebec Montreal]
On: 12 December 2007
Access Details: [subscription number 768615325]
Publisher: Routledge
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954
Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK
Social Epistemology
A Journal of Knowledge, Culture and Policy
Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:
http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713765921
"Please, Don't Let Me Be Misunderstood": The Role of
Argumentation in a Sociology of Academic
Misunderstandings
Yves Gingras
Online Publication Date: 01 October 2007
To cite this Article: Gingras, Yves (2007) '"Please, Don't Let Me Be Misunderstood":
The Role of Argumentation in a Sociology of Academic Misunderstandings', Social
Epistemology, 21:4, 369 - 389
To link to this article: DOI: 10.1080/02691720701746607
URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02691720701746607
PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE
Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf
This article maybe used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction,
re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly
forbidden.
The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be
complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be
independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings,
demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or
arising out of the use of this material.
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
Social Epistemology
Vol. 21, No. 4, October–December 2007, pp. 369–389
“Please, Don’t Let Me Be
Misunderstood”: The Role of
Argumentation in a Sociology of
Academic Misunderstandings
Yves Gingras
YvesGringas
Social
10.1080/02691720701746607
TSEP_A_274617.sgm
0269-1728
Original
Taylor
402007
21
[email protected]
00000October–December
Epistemology
&
Article
Francis
(print)/1464-5297
2007
(online)
and
Francis Ltd
Academic debates are so frequent and omnipresent in most disciplines, particularly the
social sciences and humanities, it seems obvious that disagreements are bound to occur. The
aim of this paper is to show that whereas the agent who perceives his/her contribution as
being misunderstood locates the origin of the communication problem on the side of the
receiver who “misinterprets” the text, the emitter is in fact also contributing to the possibility of this misunderstanding through the very manner in which his/her text is written.
In other words, I propose a symmetric approach to understanding misunderstandings:
taking simultaneously into account the position of the reader in the scientific field and the
structure of the texts of the writers. The paper thus proposes to complement the sociological
analysis of controversies in a scientific field with the close reading of texts, a practice usually
found in studies of argumentation, in order to explain the occurrence of misunderstandings. The debate surrounding the charge of “relativism” among sociologists of scientific
knowledge provides us with a case study to analyse in detail the argumentative context of
misunderstanding.
Keywords: Strong program; Argumentation; Controversies; Academic Misunderstanding;
Sociology of Scientific Knowledge (SSK)
Academic debates, either in print or in formal or informal discussions, are so frequent
and omnipresent in most disciplines, particularly the social sciences and humanities, it
seems obvious that disagreements are bound to occur. When not resolved by some
clarification or concession, they are most of the times spontaneously explained in
Yves Gingras is Canada Research Chair in history and sociology of sciences at CIRST UQAM. Correspondence to:
Yves Gingras, Professeur, Département d’histoire, Chaire de recherche du Canada en histoire et sociologie des
sciences, CIRST, UQAM, C.P. 8888 Suc Centre-Ville, Montréal, Québec, Canada H3C 3P8. Email:
[email protected]
ISSN 0269–1728 (print)/ISSN 1464–5297 (online) © 2007 Taylor & Francis
DOI: 10.1080/02691720701746607
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
370
Y. Gingras
terms of conflicting methodologies, paradigms or ideological commitments, taking for
granted the transparency of the argumentative structure of the texts. Although the
literature on scientific controversies is huge,1 scarce attention seems to have been
devoted to the fact that the agents involved in debates frequently invoke being “misunderstood” by their critics. The existing literature on this question is essentially limited
to linguistic analysis of oral communication between two agents of the same (or different) culture and language, and few papers address in any detail misunderstandings
based on written communication. In the oral context, misunderstandings can be
generated by a variety of mechanisms related to phonology, syntax, semantics or pragmatics (Blum-Kulka and Weizman 1988; Zaefferer 1977). Also, these treatments
usually focus on the receiver (hearer) and scant attention is given to the producer
(emitter) of discourse.2 In the oral context, cultural and linguistic habits can also
explain many misunderstandings of an otherwise well-formed sentence (Jung 2006).
As for written communication, it is more constrained than the oral one and if we leave
aside typographical errors—which are usually taken care of by a charitable interpretation of the immediate context of the sentence—the syntax and, above all, the semantics
are the main locus of possible misunderstandings. At the pragmatic level, various
reasons may be invoked to explain misunderstandings, such as being ignorant of the
topic discussed or not familiar with the technical vocabulary used by the opponent.
This type of explanation is more likely to be put forward when the participants are
from different fields or even subfields and take for granted different meanings of some
of the terms involved in the debate. Here the pragmatic context is related to the sociology of the interaction, and it is this connection that I want to make in this paper. What
interests me here is to look at a case where the complaints about being misunderstood
come from agents that are part of the same subfield and even the same paradigm.3
Having such a homogeneous group permits one to leave aside the usual obvious
reasons of misunderstanding and concentrate on an aspect that is rarely analysed in
sociology of science, although it is, I think, central to scholarly communication: the
role played by the structure of the texts themselves—that is, their argumentative structure—in contributing to misunderstandings. Using Pierre Bourdieu’s concept of a
scientific field (Bourdieu 2004) having its specific rules and legitimate forms of argumentations we can connect two aspects usually separated in the literature on rhetoric
and that on scientific controversies: whereas the former concentrates on the linguistic
aspects and takes the sociological context as given, the latter focuses on the social
aspects leaving aside the formal properties of the texts. In the large domain of rhetorical analysis, I follow the tradition that is more interested in the structure of the
argumentation itself than in the identification of the different tropes used in the texts,
although of course both aspects are present in most texts (Eemeren and Grootendorst
2004; Perelman 1997; Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca 1988). Moreover, I will also
usually stick to the word “argumentation” instead of “rhetoric” in order to avoid the
negative connotation attached to the latter and to insist on the dialogical and intersubjective nature of communication.4 Although attentive to the internal structure of the
texts being debated by the agents, the overall approach remains sociological in that it
locates the texts and their authors in the structure of the scientific field.
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
Social Epistemology 371
My aim in this paper is to show that whereas the agent who perceives his or her
contribution as being misunderstood locates the origin of the communication problem
on the side of the receiver who “misinterprets” the text, the emitter is in fact also
contributing to the possibility of this misunderstanding through the very manner in
which his text is written. I thus propose to complement the sociological analysis of
controversies in a scientific field with the close reading of texts, an approach usually
found in studies of argumentation, in order to explain the occurrence of misunderstandings. For only by taking simultaneously into account the context of production
and the context of reception can we get a complete understanding of successful as well
as failed communication.5 The debate surrounding the charge of “relativism” among
sociologists of scientific knowledge (SSK) provides us with a case study to analyse in
detail the argumentative context of misunderstanding. As a general rule, I will restrict
my analysis to criticisms formulated by agents within the field of SSK and omit those
put forward by scientists and philosophers; not because of their lack of relevance, but
because they are more complex to analyse given their heterogeneous origins. A general
analysis of all the heterogeneous agents involved in this debate would have to take into
account the larger intellectual field and would divert us from our primary purpose.6
Moreover, my interest being in understanding misunderstandings, it is much easier to
explain (away) those of outsiders than insiders. In the former case, answering “they just
don’t understand” could be considered an adequate rebuttal to counter their criticisms
as coming from agents outside the field and thus with limited, superficial or even
inexistent knowledge of sociological practice.7 As David Bloor himself noted about
some misinterpretations of the strong programme in SSK, “such errors might be
expected from ill informed critics from outside the field” (Bloor 1999, 111). One could
also, as suggested by Steven Shapin, explain these misunderstandings by the different
“disciplinary intensions” of scientists and social scientists (Shapin 2001, 102). In any
case, the acrimonious tone of many exchanges with scientists confirms Aristotle’s
advice in The Topics: “Do not argue with every one, nor practice upon the man in the
street: for there are some people with whom any argument is bound to degenerate. […]
Therefore the best rule is, not lightly to engage with the man in the street, or bad
argument is sure to result. For you see how in practicing together people cannot refrain
from contentious argument” (Aristotle 1984, 277).
So, whereas “external” attacks can often be ignored with good reasons, the situation
is quite different when the same charges of “relativism” or “idealism” come from
colleagues who, until recently at any rate, seemed to belong to the same “constructivist
camp”. In this case, one cannot invoke disciplinary distance and, short of concluding
that the strong programme is inherently incomprehensible or that the critical readers
are incompetent or disingenuous, it seems to me that part of the answer must be sought
in the narrative structure of the texts themselves. Whereas, as we shall see below, Bloor
attempted to explain the misunderstandings of his views by invoking Bartlett’s psychological law of “conventionalisation”, thus locating their source entirely on the side of
the receiver, I wish to sketch a complementary explanation that puts part of the
possibility of misreading on the side of the transmitters, thus taking seriously the
argumentative structure of their texts. In other words, I propose a symmetric approach
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
372
Y. Gingras
to understanding misunderstandings: taking simultaneously into account the position
of the reader in the scientific field (here SSK) and the structure of the texts of the writers.
In that sense, the proposed explanation is not opposed to that of Bloor but
complementary, as it brings a dimension of communication that is taken for granted
as transparent and unproblematic whereas in fact it often plays a crucial role in
generating misunderstandings and should be analysed as such.
Before proposing this analysis of the argumentative structure of some classic texts
and debates that takes into account the phenomenology of reading, I will first recall the
key criticisms voiced by major players in the SSK subfield who accused some of their
colleagues of not taking “reality” into account in their analysis of science. This will be
followed by a presentation of David Bloor’s proposed explanation of the “misunderstanding” of the Strong Program based on the views of the psychologist Frederick
Bartlett. I will then proceed to a close reading of exemplary texts to show how the
structure of the sentences contributed to the misunderstandings, thus formulating a
brief phenomenology of reading.
Constructivist Self-criticism
After a decade of intense intellectual activity, running roughly from 1975 to 1985,
followed by a period of diversification (1986–1992), SSK entered a period of
conceptual disorientation and intense internal and external debates.8
Thus, after a first decade of internal consensus over the “social construction of
science”, fairly strong criticisms started issuing from the “actor-network” movement,9
first set in motion by Michel Callon, Bruno Latour and John Law. Indeed, as early as
1987, in an implicit reference to the strong programme, Law wrote: “to try to reduce
an explanation of the Portuguese system to a limited number of social categories would
be to fail to explain the specificity of the volta, the caravel or the Regimento” (Law 1987,
131). These boats are material objects that are, Law assures us, necessary to explain
Portugal’s maritime expansion. In a similar way and that same year, Latour wrote that
“since the settlement of a controversy is the cause of Society’s stability, we cannot use
Society to explain how and why a controversy has been settled” (Latour 1987, 144).
Pretending to “generalize” the principle of symmetry that Bloor had introduced to
permit sociological explanations of the content of science, Latour had thus proposed
that “we should consider symmetrically the efforts to enrol humans and non-human
resources” (Latour 1987, 144). Similar criticisms also appeared in a text published by
Michel Callon (1986).
Following a different route, Andy Pickering also came to impute to the strong
programme a social relativism that completely failed to consider the material dimension of science. Before joining the strong programme’s critics, Pickering had published
in 1984 an exemplary application of Barnes’ sociology of interests to the case of elementary particles physics (Pickering 1984).10 In Pickering’s narrative, the constraints or
resistances of reality played no explanatory role. Only variables related to social interests were employed to explain the existence or the non-existence of phenomena such
as neutral currents or the fractional electric charges of quarks, thus characterising them
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
Social Epistemology 373
as merely the effects of a consensus that was obtained within the scientific community.11 In 1993, in an article entitled “The Mangle of Practice”, which also served as the
title of his 1995 book, Pickering “confessed” the error of his youth and denounced the
strong programme for having eliminated the material dimension from the study of
scientific practice. Indeed, according to Pickering, “the problem is that SSK makes it
impossible to take material agency seriously. The other side of SSK’s focus on human
agency is precisely the invisibility of material agency” (Pickering 1995, 10).12
Whereas these skirmishes were limited essentially to the subfields of SSK and
philosophy of science, the publication in 1994 of Paul R. Gross’ and Norman Levitt’s
polemical book Higher Superstition moved the debate into the wider intellectual field
and associated media (Gross and Levitt 1994). These external attacks on constructivist
sociology of science denounced its “post-modern” orientation (whatever that term
may mean), and launched what came to be known as the “science wars”. Beginning in
the spring of 1996, the “Sokal affair” exacerbated the controversy over the so-called
“relativism” of constructivist sociology by popularising the issue in daily newspapers,
thus oversimplifying it beyond what had already been achieved by Higher Superstition,
a book that had inspired Sokal.13 Building on the momentum provided by the Sokal
affair, Gross and Levitt published that same year the collective work The Flight from
Science and Reason, which continued their attack, indiscriminately associating SSK
with the North American cultural studies movement (Gross, Levitt and Lewis 1996).14
Much attention has already been paid to the “realism–relativism” debate, which
mostly pitted philosophers and scientists against the “relativistic” analyses of constructivist sociologists. I have no intention here of contributing to this debate, nor even to
discuss the strong programme’s epistemological and methodological foundations.15
Rather, I wish to analyse an internal debate in which central figures of SSK have accused
their peers of the very same “relativism”, and even “idealism”, that scientists and
philosophers had so often directed at them over the past 25 years. For this debate raises
an intriguing question: How can we explain the fact that the founders of the “strong
programme”, Barry Barnes and David Bloor, are now saying that they have never
denied the influence of reality in the production of scientific knowledge and that they
have in fact been grossly misunderstood? The question is all the more interesting since
Bloor has gone so far as to charge his colleague Bruno Latour with interpreting his work
in ways that are utterly “incomprehensible” coming from such a “central” figure of the
field (Bloor 1999, 111). Similarly, but without giving names, Barnes believes that a
certain form of “misinformation” has been “actively encouraged by cynical academics
hostile to [the Edinburgh] approach” (Barnes 1998, 637). But before trying to understand how such a misunderstanding can occur among a relatively homogeneous group,
let us look at Bloor’s response to these “attacks”.
Bloor Strikes Back
Although the criticisms of “relativism” and “idealism” had been circulating for over a
decade, it was only in 1999 that Bloor decided to respond energetically to his detractors/colleagues. Until then, his defence of the strong programme had been essentially
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
374
Y. Gingras
targeted at philosophers’ criticisms. He now concentrated his attack on Latour, who,
in his eyes, represents the best example of someone having completely misunderstood
the nature of the strong programme. In fact, Bloor ends up concluding that Latour
“belongs to the ranks of those like the recent contributors to The Flight From Science
and Reason (Gross et al., 1996) who have only to see the label ‘sociology of knowledge’
to conclude that its doctrine must imply the absurdity that knowledge is ‘purely
social’” (Bloor 1999, 110). The reference to this book strongly suggests a link between
the “science wars” and this new phase of SSK’s internal debates. It is indeed difficult
to avoid the impression that Bloor’s decision to finally enter the debate16 is in large
part dictated by these external events and appears as a reaction to attacks by scientists
and other intellectuals, which had taken on considerable proportions with the
“science war” and had also had, in the United States at least, concrete institutional
repercussions.17
Whatever the exact role of the “science wars” played in the origin of this dispute, it
is interesting to note that in their book Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis,
Barnes, Bloor, and Henry (1996) also directed their attack at another major actor
within the SSK field: Harry Collins. Indeed, they accuse Collins of “methodological
idealism” and of adopting a “relativistic” position that denies the existence of natural
causes in the closure of scientific debates. Recall that, for Collins, the sociologist must
study science as if the natural world played no role in the production of knowledge.
Although clearly polemical, this methodological thesis was of course not new in 1996.
It had first appeared as far back as 1981 in a programmatic text in which Collins
proclaimed that “the natural world in no way constrains what is believed to be” (Collins
1981a, p. 54; emphasis added). A slightly different (and more ambiguous) formulation
was given in a short introduction to the collection of papers in which the preceding
formulation appears: “the natural world has a small or non-existent role in the construction of scientific knowledge” (Collins 1981b, p. 3; emphasis added). Two years later he
used the formula: “the natural world must be treated as though it did not affect our
perception of it” (Collins 1983, p. 88; emphasis added), which has still another meaning.
Reflecting on these expressions, Collins now sees no reason to change anything “except
for a few rhetorical flourishes” (Collins 2004, 797).18 But from the point of view of
argumentation adopted here, what Collins seems to consider “rhetorical flourishes”
were of course read as serious arguments (or at least statements) by most readers
(including scientists and philosophers) who usually take it for granted that writers
know their grammar and do mean what they say and what they write. As I suggested
elsewhere (Gingras 2007), one can even suggest that without these “flourishes” there
would hardly have ever been any “science war”; no “unpleasant war of words between
a group of self-appointed spokespersons for science and the social scientists”, to use
Collins’ words (Collins 2004, 793).
Coming back to Bloor and his colleagues, it is intriguing that they waited 15 years
before denouncing Collins as an “idealist”. And it is worth noting that, from a rhetorical point of view, castigating him as “idealist” implicitly suggests that the strong
programme is, by contrast, “materialist” and that it consequently takes into
consideration the existence of the natural world in its sociological explanations of how
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
Social Epistemology 375
knowledge is produced. For Bloor and his colleagues insist that: “Pace Collins and his
interesting idealist arguments, sociologists should be willing to acknowledge the
existence and the causal relevance of the physical environment when they study the
growth of knowledge” (Barnes, Bloor and Henry 1996, 76; emphasis added).
Moving from principles to concrete applications, the authors criticise Collins’ and
Pinch’s analysis of a controversy over the existence of extra-sensory perception (ESP).
There, Collins and Pinch had claimed to be able to explain the absence of consensus in
the field in a perfectly symmetrical way, noting that the “believers” interpreted the negative experimental results as examples of real phenomena that simply failed to occur,
while the “unbelievers” considered these negative results as proof that such paranormal
phenomena simply do not exist. Contrary to Collins and Pinch, who say nothing about
the possible “reality” of the contested phenomena, Bloor and his colleagues suggest that
“it was probably because of the state of the material world in the context of the experiment
that ESP was considered absent” (Barnes, Bloor and Henry 1996, 76). Thus, Collins and
Pinch propose a social cause precisely where Bloor and his collaborators advance a material one. As my goal is not to defend Collins and Pinch, nor to discuss the validity of the
symmetry principle, I simply wish to point out that the alternative explanation proposed
is somewhat surprising from an SSK perspective, since it is founded upon the absence
of a result, which, as Collins and Pinch noted, is an entirely circumstantial outcome from
the point of view of the actors involved. To invoke “the state of the material world” is
to abandon the actors’ point of view and to violate the symmetry principle by adopting
in fact the position of an “unbeliever”. As we shall later see, it is the very absence of an
empirical signal (as in the case of gravitational waves) that ensures the plausibility (and
possibility) of the symmetrical analysis of ESP proposed by Collins and Pinch.
Conversely, it is the intervention of a material cause through an unambiguous positive
signal (as in the case of the Transverse Electric Atmospheric (TEA) laser, discussed
below) that allows one to escape from the experimenter’s regress, thus breaking the
symmetry. But these logical points are not perceived by Bloor and his colleagues.
Bloor’s analysis tends to remain at the level of general principles and rarely addresses
the narrative detail of the case in question. But it is important to first clearly distinguish
general statements of principle that abstractly affirm the importance (or not) of “reality” in the construction of knowledge from the actual empirical studies and their narrative structure. For, if I am correct in believing that the misunderstandings are partly
explained by the specific formulations offered to the reader, it is only by carefully analysing the argumentative structure of existing case studies that we will be in a position
to determine whether the authors are relativists or not in the explanatory narratives of
their texts. In other words: instead of asking a metaphysical question about “reality” or
trying to know whether Bloor or Collins really believe in the external world, I propose
to search for the exact role any element of “reality” plays in the narratives they offer of
the phenomena they analyse. From this point of view, as we shall now see for the case
of the successful construction of a TEA-CO2 laser, Collins is sometimes less “idealistic”
than he seems in his more programmatic statements (quoted above).
In his study of the final development of the TEA-CO2 laser, Collins’ narrative explicitly invoked the material world as a factor in forging the consensus surrounding the
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
376
Y. Gingras
laser’s success. He writes: “the experimenter’s regress did not make itself apparent […]
because in the case of the TEA-laser, the circle was readily broken. The ability of the laser
to vaporise concrete, or whatever, comprised a universally agreed [upon] criterion of
experiment quality” (Collins 1985, 84; emphasis added). In this brief sentence on
which Collins does not insist, the laser’s physical properties are presented as the cause
for believing that the laser works. This example, unique to Collins’ work, suffices to
illustrate the potential difference between methodological or programmatic statements
and the causal structure of a particular narrative account. What clearly stops the discussion on the working or not of the laser is not any social interest but the very fact that
coherent electromagnetic waves intrudes in a spectacular way by evaporating any material on its path. By contrast, what makes credible relativist-looking narratives in the
case of ESP or gravitational waves is the fact that they have not yet been detected in any
comparable spectacular way. In other words, it has rarely been noted that it is only these
open and undecided cases that allow Collins to adhere to the “relativistic thesis within
which consideration of the ‘actual existence’ of a phenomenon is redundant” (Collins
and Pinch 1979, 262–263). “Reality” can indeed appear to be superfluous (in a
contingent way and up to now) for phenomena such as ESP and gravitational waves but
not for the TEA laser.
Another manner to implicitly suggest a relativist posture is exemplified by Trevor
Pinch when he disputes Martin Rudwick’s assertion that empirical data played a decisive role in closing the controversy over the nature of the Devonian period in the
history of mid-19th-century British geology. Although he recognises that Rudwick is
receptive to the constructivist approach, Pinch nonetheless sees him attributing a much
more important role to nature than SSK proponents normally do. He thus tries to show
that it is precisely for this reason that Rudwick’s conclusions are unconvincing. Again,
my goal here is not to take side in this controversy, but to draw attention to the fact
that, by concentrating his attack on Rudwick’s “realism”, Pinch ends up suggesting
implicitly that a convincing SSK analysis cannot grant a causal role to empirical data
(Pinch 1986, 711).19
Bloor on Bartlett’s Law
In view of these accusations of “relativism” and “idealism” coming from some of the
pillars of social constructivism, it seems hardly necessary to recall the numerous
“denunciations” of relativism or even of “obscurantism” from scientists or rationalist
philosophers.20 Let us instead return to our opening question: How are we to explain
such “misunderstandings” between presumably well-informed parties? Despite the
many papers devoted to the “realist–relativist” debate, most are contributions to the
debate itself and few try to offer a distanced sociological analysis, taking as it were
the very debate as an object instead of participating in it. An exception is David Bloor
who instead of just adding fuel to the debate took some distance to propose an
explanation based on Bartlett’s second law, named after the British psychologist
Sir Frederic Charles Bartlett (1886–1969), author of an important study on memory
(Bartlett 1932). This law, also referred to as “conventionalisation”, describes how
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
Social Epistemology 377
agents have a tendency to simplify the stories they have heard (or read) so as to render
them decreasingly dependent on the culture of origin and increasingly compatible
with the agent’s own culture. Moreover, over the course of recalling and retelling, the
story takes on new characteristics that are specific to the agent’s own culture and
absent from the original version. In short, the original formulation tends to be
reinterpreted in the context and in accord with the culture of the receiving agent
(Bloor 1997, 375). Thus, when Stephen Cole (1998) reduced Bloor’s position to that of
a neo-Marxist—even though the targeted article was entitled “Durkheim and Mauss
revisited” (not Marx …)—and oversimplified his analysis of how Boyle and Newton
came to believe in the passivity of matter, the American sociologist was succumbing,
for polemical reasons, to Bartlett’s law of conventionalisation (Bloor 1999, 376).21
One can hardly deny the existence of this process of oversimplification and schematisation, often accentuated by polemical posturing, in the debates between supporters
and opponents of constructivism.22 I believe, however, there are other processes at
work that can better explain why some authors seem to be so misunderstood. Indeed,
while Bartlett’s law locates the process on the side of the receiver, I think that the basis
for the misunderstanding also lies on the side of the transmitter of the message, or more
precisely in the narrative and explanatory structures of the texts themselves. Bazzanella
and Damiano identify different types of “triggers” that generate misunderstanding, and
ambiguity is one of the most important of them (Bazzanella and Damiano 1999, 818),
cultural differences being another one. Thus, one should expect that, in written texts,
the misunderstandings will in large part be triggered by: (1) the ambiguous formulation (conscious or not) of some statements of principle that allow for at least two
readings, one benign (if not trivial) and the other radical; (2) the confusion, during
polemical exchanges, between statements of principle and the actual content of case
studies, as if they were equivalent; and, finally, (3) the gap between theoretical
intentions (formulated in the general principles) and the effective narrative structure
of case studies based on these principles, some agents moving from one to the other
without indicating it.
Adopting here the neutral posture of the observer, I will eschew the moral tone
expressed in the use of terms such as “cynical” or “misinformation” and try to propose
instead cognitive and sociological reasons that take into account the argumentative
structure of the texts. We thus leave open the question as to whether or not some of the
actors involved in the debate are “cynical”, for the simple reason that it is very difficult
to test such imputations of motives. By limiting our analysis to a homogeneous group
of actors in a scientific field, we take for granted that they obey the rules of the field and
do not wilfully act in a cynical manner.23 If the latter were the case, they would simply
breach the implicit communication contract, which, as Marcelo Dascal noted, “rests on
mutual trust between responsible individuals” (Dascal 1999, 757). In that sense, this
strong implicit contract based on the presumptions of trust and responsibility is such
that it would be legitimate “to view those use of language that deliberately violate [these
presumptions] as morally—not just technically—wrong since they involve a breach of
trust”. Although one could study “the moral implications of manipulative practices
that evade communicative responsibility” (Dascal 1999, 757), I will not do that here
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
378
Y. Gingras
and limit myself to making visible the argumentative strategies that may trigger misunderstandings, whether these uses are conscious or not. It is up to the reader to impute
motivations if he/she so wishes, but that does not affect the analysis proposed here.
Radicality Effects
Before focusing more narrowly on the narrative and explanatory structure of certain
key texts, let us briefly recall some of the textual features associated with general statements of principle—usually found in introductions and conclusions—that contribute
to explain the “exaggerated” reactions of certain readers and their “profoundly incomprehensible” reading of SSK texts. I have noted elsewhere (Gingras 1995) the tendency
to play on the meaning of words and to confound, for example, a relation with an identity, thus allowing the reduction of “science” to “politics”. Following Olga Amsterdamska (1990), Bloor has also noted Latour’s tendency to play on the meaning of words,
moving from “nature” to the “representation of nature” as if these formulations were
synonymous. Bloor points out that SSK acknowledges the existence of nature and is
only interested in the representations verbalised by scientists; that is, in their beliefs
regarding nature. It is because they failed to see this distinction between “reality” and
“knowledge of reality”, he argues, that critics perceived SSK as a form of idealism,
whereas the programme in fact embraces both materialism and naturalism (Bloor
1999, 87).
Brief programmatic statements that are sufficiently ambiguous to enable the writer
to charge any would-be opponents with misunderstanding them often provoke the
anger of scientists and rationalist philosophers. Take Collins’ three different statements
already cited. The first, which affirms that “the natural world in no way constrains what
is believed to be” (Collins 1981a, 54; emphasis added), is indeed radical (“in no way
constrains”) and was even considered (and denounced) as “absurd” by some sociologists (Cole 1998, 275), not to mention physicists.24 The second version, written the
same year, suggesting that “the natural world has a small or non-existent role in the
construction of scientific knowledge” (Collins 1981b, 3; emphasis added), is already
opening the door to a role (albeit small) for reality. Finally, the third, which suggests
that “the natural world must be treated as though it did not affect our perception of it”
(Collins 1983, 88; emphasis added), reflects more clearly the methodological nature of
the statement. By contrast, the first statement having no qualifying clause such as
“must be treated as though” can only be read as an ontological statement (“nature in no
way constrains”); the only way to interpret it otherwise would be to invoke external
factors like “I know the guy and what he means is methodological”. The internal logic
of the first two statements does not give this information (as the third statement did),
and any charitable reinterpretation must invoke ad hoc assumptions (like “careless
writing”) or “strategic manoeuvring” in order to justify not taking them at face value.
Now, let us see how a sociologist of science trained in the SSK paradigm reads an
ambiguous statement about the role of reality in knowledge construction. In his
critique of SSK, Pickering’s picks up a short statement by Barnes: “Reality will tolerate
alternative descriptions without protest. We may say what we will of it, and it will not
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
Social Epistemology 379
disagree. Sociologists of knowledge rightly reject realist epistemologies that empower
reality” (Barnes 1994, 331).25 This statement is (consciously or not) intrinsically ambiguous. In a strict but trivial sense, it is true: reality cannot protest against what we say of
it for the simple reason that it cannot talk. In a figurative sense, however—which is
most of the time the way such metaphors are used and interpreted in ordinary
language26—such a statement suggests that a scientific discourse (theory) need not be
related to reality, which seems to be how Pickering understood it since he denounced
it as being a relativistic thesis. Again, the point is not to agree or disagree with Barnes
(or any other sociologist for that matter) but to note that the very structure of the
sentence provides the material basis that makes possible Pickering’s interpretation,
which cannot simply be dismissed as a “mistaken” reading.
We shave a similar situation in David Mermin’s review of the book written by
Barnes, Bloor and Henry. Commenting on the proposition that even a discipline as
rigorous as mathematics can in fact conceal flagrant contradictions that go unnoticed
by students, these authors write: “People have apparently found little problem in
accepting that a circle is a line, notwithstanding it has a finite area” (Barnes, Bloor and
Henry 1996, 64). In his review, Mermin, a physicist, noted that the use of such ambiguous formulations give a radical tone to statements that would otherwise be totally
banal. He writes: “this sounds less paradoxical and considerably less interesting if you
say instead: ‘people find little problem in accepting the use of a single term to describe
either a line or the region of finite area bounded by that line, because the intended
meaning is almost invariably clear in the context’” (Mermin 1998, 609).27 As before, it
seems clear that the very structure of the sentence does contain the possibility of
suggesting both interpretations to the reader.
Another striking example of what we might call radicality effects is at work in declarations that objects have a history, that they are born and often die, as Lorraine Daston
writes in her introduction to a book on Biographies of Scientific Objects: “This is a book
about […] how whole domains of phenomena […] come into being and pass away as
objects of scientific inquiry” (Daston 2000, 1–2; emphasis added). In the following
paragraph we learn that “this way of understanding scientific objects […] is at odds
with the sense entrenched in the etymology of the very word ‘object’ in several major
European languages”, which suggest that these objects “are neither subtle nor evanescent nor hidden […] They do not need to be discovered or investigated […]”. Finally,
we are told that “an ontology that is true to objects that are at once real and historical
has yet to come into being, but it is already clear that it will be an ontology in motion”.
Beyond the poetic style, the shift in meaning is pretty obvious: the author moves from
the banal observation that objects of scientific inquiry change over time to the idea that
it is objects themselves that emerge and disappear. Daston could of course allege that
she distinguishes “objects” in some technical sense from “things” in the everyday
sense, but we are still left with an intrinsic ambiguity that permits to move from one
interpretation to the other depending on the audience or the critics received. This
oscillation between “object” and “object of scientific inquiry” or “scientific objects”,
which are at once real and historical, thus astutely combining (at least in the realm of
words) the advantages of “realism” and “constructivism”, is in fact similar to Latour’s
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
380
Y. Gingras
shifts between “reality” and the “representation of reality” noted by Bloor, which
produce a radicality effect while conserving the possibility of returning to the “banal”
sense when needed. One could perhaps offer a more charitable reading, but as Alban
Bouvier observes, although the transgression of elementary rules of communication is
not incompatible with the comprehension of a text, it nonetheless “requires a cognitive (and temporal) cost that not all readers, even the well intentioned, are necessarily
ready to pay” (Bouvier 1996, 56).
Moreover, while a better control of style would eliminate such radicality effects
(when they were not intended), it would not completely exclude the kind of biased
readings that Bloor denounces. Thus, although Collins’ and Pinch’s (1979) text on
parapsychology was essentially ethnographic and neutral with regard to the actors’
epistemological positions, it could not prevent Gerald Eberlein, blinded by a “normative epistemology”, from denouncing SSK as a “new irrationalism” (Eberlein 1994,
131). This mutual incomprehension is essentially the result of a category mistake
whereby the author mistakenly applies a normative reading to what was essentially a
descriptive ethnographic text.
As the responses of rationalist philosophers to remarks by constructivist sociologists
illustrate, it would be foolish to believe in any easily obtained ideal consensus. But it is
by acknowledging that the audience (targeted or constructed) is an intrinsic part of the
process of argumentation that we may begin to explain the reception of texts beyond
the simple psychological law invoked by Bloor (Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca 1988,
22–46). It is obvious that many of the strong programme’s remarks are directed more
at philosophers than sociologists, and that many of the latter would no doubt find them
curious if not plainly outrageous. It is sufficiently clear, for example, that Sokal’s and
Bricmont’s critiques were responding more to the strong programme’s philosophical
theses than to its sociological methodology. The mertonian sociologist Stephen Cole
even believes that the tendency of constructivists to use a philosophical language could
have contributed to the fact that, unlike their counterparts in philosophy, few sociologists have actually confronted the constructivists. Cole also thinks that many constructivists, “though not all”, display an “abysmal” ignorance of the major sociological issues
(Cole 1998, 277). For Cole, it is evident that the SSK movement was created at the
margin of a sociological field, whose members are generally unmoved by relativistic
theses, as opposed to the rationalist philosophers who are quick to man the barricades
to defend any perceived attack on “reason” or “reality”. Cole’s reaction can also be
understood in sociological terms. The strong whiff of resentment emerging from his
text can be understood as the reaction of a sociologist who identifies himself more
strongly with the general field of sociology than with the SSK subfield and who sees the
constructivist “revolution” as superseding and marginalising (thus devaluating) his
own work. In point of fact, the very success of the strong programme (at the time of
Cole’s writing) completely eclipsed the mertonian approach, which was the dominant
research programme up to the mid-1970s. Likewise, the rising criticisms purporting to
show that the Strong programme is now dépassé in the field of SSK may have forced
Bloor to temporarily abandon the debate with philosophers and to take issue with
“former friends” in order to defend a threatened position in the SSK field. Thus, the
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
Social Epistemology 381
position of the agent in the field must be taken into account while interpreting a text
(Bourdieu 1988). In this way, what is often glossed as individual psychological reactions can be seen instead as the effect on a given agent of the changing sociological
configuration of the scientific field.
Even the propensity to endorse trendy arguments depends on the position of the
agent in his discipline (sociology, philosophy, etc.). Thus, new entrants in the field, for
example, have a tendency to prefer to the already established (and occupied) positions
those that seem “radical” and “new”. They may then show less concern for the detailed
internal coherence of the arguments and be more prone to use them as a weapon to
“renew” their field and attract attention, and thus create new positions for themselves
in the field. By contrast, well-established agents who feel under attack have every reason
to carefully analyse the arguments of their opponent and make visible their weaknesses
in order to defend their position. A polysemic text that is explicitly aimed at different
audiences (in this case sociologists and philosophers) is thus bound to produce
different discursive effects by virtue of its structure and the diversity of its potential
readers, who interpret the text in relation to their respective environments,
backgrounds and positions in the field (Ceccarelli 2001). As for the transmitter, even
the place of publication can influence how his or her text will be read, as journals always
presuppose a certain kind of contribution, which the readers then expect to find in the
papers appearing in those journals. Yet, all these things being equal, one must not overlook the importance of the argumentative structure of the text itself, although most
debates have paid little attention to that aspect.
Interestingly, actors often activate the dispositions necessary to make such close
readings when they are under attack, although they do not so readily apply these same
dispositions when writing their own texts. For example, in their answer to the critical
comments by Cassandra Pinnick on their book Leviathan and the Air Pump, Shapin
and Shaffer are very attentive to the effects of her text on the potential readers. Noting
that she quotes one-half of a sentence from their book and then cites “exactly the same
two passages from Hobbes that are found on that page” of the book, they add: “she thus
makes it appear that [our book] misses the agreement between Boyle and Hobbes […]
and makes it appear, too, that [our book] knows nothing of these specific passages from
Hobbes” (Shapin and Schaffer 1999, 250–251; emphasis added). Here the authors
clearly show how a given sentence can effectively suggest an interpretation to the reader
through its very structure, without having to state it explicitly. And if such an analysis
of the effects (intended or not) of the texts can be applied to opponents, then it can,
and indeed should, also be applied to our own texts in order to better control them,
since these effects follow from the phenomenology of reading.
A Brief Phenomenology of Reading
The classic works of W. B. Gallie (1964) and of Arthur C. Danto (1965) on the nature
of narrative explanation clearly identified the two major dimensions of a narrative that
make it possible to follow a story.28 All narratives propose an order and a sequence, and
the act of understanding a narrative is accomplished in a dialectical relation between its
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
382
Y. Gingras
episodic (or chronological) and configurational (or global) dimensions. To follow a
story, and therefore to understand it, is to reconstitute a whole by combining, while
reading a text (listening a story or watching a movie), these two dimensions that convey
the general meaning of the narrative. This overall understanding is informed by and
consistent with the narrative details contained within the story. To use Louis O. Mink’s
terms, to follow and understand a story consists of forming a synoptic judgement that
draws upon a configurational understanding that takes into account the whole content
of the text in a circular relation between the local and the global (Mink 1987). In other
words, historical understanding (and sociological understanding we may add) is a
combination of local (episodic) and global (configurational) dimensions. From this
perspective, the text itself contains elements that orient the very process of “conventionalisation” that Bloor invokes to explain why SSK is so often misunderstood.
Take, for instance, Barry Barnes’ foundational work, Scientific Knowledge and Sociological Theory. The way in which he speaks of “reality” in the body of the book gives the
overall impression that it is not an explanatory resource upon which the sociologist
may draw, and yet by addressing the question of the role of reality at the beginning of
the book he seems to imply the opposite. Indeed, in the very first page of the preface,
Barnes notes that: “Occasionally, existing work leaves the feeling that reality has nothing to do with what is socially constructed or negotiated to count as natural knowledge
[…] We may safely assume that this impression is an accidental by-product of overenthusiastic sociological analysis, and that sociologists as a whole acknowledge that the
world in some way constrains what it is believed to be. The question however remains:
what is the nature of this constraint and how much is it” (Barnes 1974, vii; emphasis
added).
Having encountered this question in the introduction of the book, the reader is thus
alerted to this problem and can reasonably expect to find it addressed again in the body
of the work or at least in the conclusion. But it never comes up again, and the question
of determining “the nature” of the constraint or its intensity (“how much is it?”) is left
open as the account instead focuses on the social variables that help shape a consensus
concerning reality. This kind of argumentative structure tends to suggest an implicit
answer to the reader: if reality does not explicitly intervene as an explanatory factor in
the arguments developed in the body of the text, it is probably because its role is nil, or
at the very least negligible. This interpretation is even reinforced by stylistic details.
Indeed, each time Barnes affirms the importance of external reality in scientific practice, he immediately tempers his account with a caveat. Sentences take the form “of
course, but”, which tends to emphasise the second half of the sentence where the role
played by “reality” (or “material objects”) in scientific practice affirmed in the first part
of the sentence is relativised. Barnes thus reminds us in a footnote: “Experimentation
has, of course, played a very important role in the development of science, its importance is nonetheless overrated, even within the experimental sciences” (Barnes 1974, 165;
emphasis added). Further on he adds: “the result of a piece of creative science […]
must, of course, accord with experimental findings to some extent if they are to be
accepted. But the constraint of experiment is easy to over-estimate, and its role in securing acceptance of work is never more than partial” (Barnes 1974, 88; emphasis added).
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
Social Epistemology 383
Pickering also used sentences of this type, in his study of quarks. After describing
experiments performed by many groups to confirm the existence of free quarks on
particles of tungsten that produced systematically negative results, Pickering notes that:
“As a result of these findings, the tungsten hypothesis was abandoned” (Pickering 1981,
232). And since, in such a formulation, the cause for abandoning the hypothesis would
clearly be attributed to the experimental results—an “answer” from “reality” as it were,
which would be a fairly classic explanation for a realist—Pickering adds, five sentences
later: “Nonetheless, through custom and routine use [the tungsten experiments] are
deemed sufficiently closed by the physics community and therefore evidence from
them might be deemed conclusive” (Pickering 1981, 232). Thus, in a few sentences,
Pickering transformed what first looked as a material cause (experimental results) into
a social one (tradition and habit). Let us repeat here that the point is not to criticise
such formulations but to note how they make possible the “relativist” readings on the
part of readers and provide the semantic basis of their conclusion that reality (through
experimental results) has no causal role in the narrative. Other examples would show
that the “conventionalisation” tendency noted by Bloor is rooted in the narrative structure of the texts themselves. Taken as a whole, these rare explicit formulations cannot
help but leave the reader with the impression that reality plays an insignificant role
since the sentences are constructed so as to minimise its importance, an impression
reinforced by a way of accounting that emphasises social variables as causal factors.
As linguists have shown, in forms “P but Q” the connector “but” creates an opposition that tends to minimise or even negate the role of P (Carel 1999; Ducrot 1980;
Lakoff 1971; Ponchon 1993). In the case at hand, it is the combination of the uses of
“but” and the absence of a causal role given to natural objects in the narrative that
orient readers to the conclusion that reality plays no part in explanation of science
provided in typical SSK narratives. The “but” could be interpreted as simply counterbalancing the tendency to maximise the role of reality in realist narrative only if it were
followed by examples where the resistance of objects were also mentioned positively as
constraining possible interpretations, which is not the case in most of the examples
given above. This is confirmed by Bruno Latour, who, in his reply to Bloor, notes the
absence of objects in constructivist accounts: “It is not enough to say that objects play
the role of anchor in our beliefs about the world. […] The question is to know which
role objects play. […] If you make a list of all the roles that things or sensory inputs play
in SSK’s narratives, you will be struck by the fact that they don’t do very much” (Latour
1999, 1117). Latour here reveals a major source of the misunderstanding: the question
is not to determine whether Bloor (or anybody else) is idealist or not, but to correctly
identify the precise role of objects in the causal explanations offered in SSK narratives.
Thus, if material causes are to be present as such, they should intervene in the very
narration of case studies. If the narrative focuses the reader’s attention on social variables, then the reader will conclude (and schematise) the explanation as being uniquely
social. And just as objects do rarely explicitly cause conversions in case studies of the
SSK tradition, which insists on interpretative flexibility and contingency, they are
conversely at the heart of the explanatory process in the actor-network approach, a
presence that in turn explains why the latter is perceived as a return to “realism”.
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
384
Y. Gingras
Conclusion
Taking into account the fine textual structure of narratives provides a way to a more
complete explanation of misunderstandings between agents than the approaches that
concentrate solely on the receiver end and his or her tendency to simplify an account.
For in addition to the social variables of the position of the agents in the field, their
cognitive interests and the like, one has to take into account the “logic of reading” that
is guided by the very structure of the texts themselves. So, in addition to looking at the
receiver of texts, one has also to concentrate on the transmitter of those texts and more
precisely on the linguistic structure of the texts. After all, meaning is conveyed through
sentences and, as we have seen, the presence (or absence) of a single word (or even
punctuation) can transform the possible interpretations of the text. My analysis in
terms of narrative structure suggests that in analysing debates among agents (in the
field of SSK or any other one) one should be sensitive to the fine explanatory structure
of accounts rather than concentrate on general meta-discourses that serve only to reiterate intentions that are not always put into practice. Hence, by concentrating on
general principles (which are materialistic), Barnes and Bloor could claim to having
been “misunderstood” by their adversaries whose attention was in fact directed toward
the actual content and implicit explanatory structure of their case studies.
In short, in a truly reflexive practice, the art of reading must be combined with a
mastery of writing and its effects. And whatever the intensions of authors, a poor
mastery of the art of writing—or a conscious play on words in order to generate
polysemic readings to attract more readers—can only lead to misunderstandings. Once
the form is brought properly under control, authors and their critics may finally be in
a better position to seriously address the content of these texts and engage in meaningful intellectual exchanges that avoid unproductive misunderstandings. They might
then finally be able to at least agree on exactly what they disagree about and why.
Acknowledgements
The author wishes to thank Peter Keating, Claude Rosental, Wiktor Stoczkowski and
Simon Schaffer for their comments on an earlier draft of this paper. The author also
wishes to thank David Bloor for his comments on an earlier draft, although he does not
agree with the presented analysis. Thanks also to Steve Fuller for his encouragement,
and the reviewers of Social Epistemology for their useful comments. This paper further
develops an analysis first presented in Gingras (2000).
Notes
1
2
3
[1] For en entry into this literature, see Engelhardt and Caplan (1987) or browse issues of this
journal or Social Studies of Science.
[2] For a recent survey of the linguistic analysis of misunderstandings, see Weigand (1999).
[3] I am not interested here in the hypothetical and metaphysical case imagined by Steve Fuller of
“misunderstandings” that are not detected as such and could thus “persist for long periods
because the parties are using much the same language, yet to mean systematically different
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
Social Epistemology 385
4
[4]
5
[5]
[6]
6
7
8
9
[7]
[8]
[9]
[10]
[11]
[12]
10
11
12
[13]
13
[14]
14
things” (Fuller 1988, 129). I am interested in empirical cases where the misunderstanding is
explicitly perceived and stated by one of the parties involved in the discussion.
By doing this, we are conscious that we lose the symbolic profit of radicality associated with
talks of “rhetoric of science”; the expression “argumentation in science” looking more traditional and rationalistic. It is significant that the title of the French version of Perelman and
Olbrechts-Tyteca (1988) is “Treatise of argumentation” with the subtitle “The New Rhetoric”,
whereas the English translation used the subtitle as the main title, thus reversing the original
choice of the authors by putting the emphasis on rhetoric instead of argumentation. For a
survey of the literature on “rhetoric of science”, see Gross (1996). For a recent survey of the
vast literature on argumentation theory, see Tindale (1999) and Doury and Moirand (2005).
For an exemplary case linking production of texts and their reception, see Ceccarelli (2001).
For example, it is striking that in their introduction to the book The One Culture? A Conversation About Science (Labinger and Collins 2001), the editors Jay A. Labinger and Harry Collins
say nothing about the “culture wars” that raged in the USA at the beginning of the 1990s and
that clearly paved the way for the “science wars”. None of the other contributors seem to be
aware of that context, and most make a rather artificial link with the old 1950s “two cultures”
debate of C. P. Snow, which has hardly anything in common with the culture and science
wars. But this is not the place to develop this analysis, since a convincing one would have to
take into account the specificity of each country: for example, the “Sokal Affair” in the USA
has a totally different dynamic and meaning than its namesake in France. On the culture wars
that preceded the science wars, see Linenthal and Engelhardt (1996) and Nash, Crabtree and
Dunn (1997).
For an example of academic misunderstandings based in part on gender, see Tickner (1997).
Traces of these debates can be found in this journal and also in Social Studies of Science. The
locus classicus of a first wave of debate is the collective book published under the direction of
Andy Pickering (1992).
More often referred to as ANT for “actor-network theory”. Although I cannot develop that
point of view here, I think that this approach is not a theory in any standard epistemological
sense, but simply a descriptive language. It would thus be more precise to call it “actornetwork language” or, to use an acronym, ANL.
His methodological ressources were Barnes (1974, 1977).
For a detailed analysis of Pickering’s book, see Gingras and Schweber (1986).
The confession is in note 15 at the bottom of the page. For a detailed analysis of the book, see
Gingras (1997), and the exchanges that followed in Pickering (1999) and Gingras (1999).
For preliminary analyses of the Sokal Affair written in the heat of the debate, see Hilgartner
(1997), Lynch (1997), Dubois (1998), Feldman (1999) and Jeanneret (1998).
See also Koertege (1998). For a series of exchanges between some of the authors of this book
and those they critique, see Social Studies of Science, volume 29, number 2 (April 1999). It
would be illuminating to study more precisely how cultural studies appropriated the work of
SSK. All signs point to a largely one-way “phagocytic” relationship of the former with the latter.
From a strictly bibliometric perspective, one can readily see that the canonical cultural studies
journals have just about never been cited in the leading SSK journals (Social Studies of Science,
and Science Technology and Human Values), while authors connected to the sociology of
science movement are widely cited by cultural studies partisans, who are often located in
American University departments of languages and literature. Thus a journal like Social Text,
which Sokal qualified as “prestigious”, was in fact rather obscure at the time and has been made
“famous” by Sokal’s very hoax. It does not figure among the network of journals cited by Social
Studies of Science. As shown in the Journal Citation Reports published by Thomson Scientific,
this network includes journals such as Scientometrics, Science Technology and Human Values,
Isis, Research Policy and other similar journals closely associated with science and technology
studies. For analyses of the American context of cultural studies, see Wacquant (1997) and
Pierssens (1988). On the ties between cultural studies and sociology, see McLennan (1998).
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
386
Y. Gingras
[15] For a recent attempt of this genre, see Tosh (2006).
[16] I refer here to the debate inside SSK as opposed to the usual debates with philosophers.
[17] See, for example, the overview of the debates in Nature, volume 387 (22 May 1997, 331–335)
and in The Economist (13 December 1997, 79).
[18] For another “autobiographical” explanation by Collins of that oft-quoted remark, see
Labinger and Collins (2001, 184).
[19] For a critique of the validity of Pinch’s arguments against Rudwick, see Gingras (1995).
[20] For a sample of these criticisms, see Gross and Levitt (1994), Gross, Levitt and Lewis (1996),
Koertege (1998), Boudon and Clavelin (1994).
[21] The reference to “voodoo” in the title of Cole’s article clearly flags its polemical character.
[22] The tendency to reduce choices to a dichotomy where there is in fact a continuum of positions
is analysed in Boudon (1994).
[23] For a model of argumentation in a scientific field, see Godin and Gingras (2002).
[24] For Collins recent “autobiographical” explanation of that oft-quoted remark, see Labinger
and Collins (2001, 184, note 1).
[25] Cited in Pickering (1995, 10, note 16). In a more recent article, Barnes (1999, 55) takes up
essentially the same formulation: “reality itself, needless to say, is indifferent to how it is
oriented to or described, and never voices any dissatisfaction with whatever specific
construction is put upon it”.
[26] Here is an example: talking about the interpretation of new astrophysical data, a scientist told
a journalist: “It’s always possible the universe is trying to tell us something”. It is obvious that
readers of The New Scientist (2 July 2005, 35; emphasis added), in which this interview
appeared, spontaneously understood that he meant that the data could suggest a new
interpretation, not that the universe was really trying to tell us something or that the scientist
was a kind of mystic who really thought the universe was indeed talking to him.
[27] Note that this review was prepared at the invitation of the editor, David Edge, as a gesture to
facilitate direct exchange between scientists and SSK scholars in the aftermath of the “science
wars”.
[28] For a more recent discussion, see Ricœur (1984).
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
References
Amsterdamska, O. 1990. Surely you are joking Monsieur Latour! Science, Technology and Human
Values 15 (1): 495–504.
Aristotle. 1984. Topics. Book VIII. In The complete works of Aristotle, edited by Jonathan Barnes
(revised Oxford translation). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Barnes, B. 1974. Scientific knowledge and sociological theory. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Barnes, B. 1977. Interests and the growth of knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Barnes, B. 1994. How not to do sociology of knowledge. In Rethinking objectivity, edited by Allan
Megill. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Barnes, B. 1998. Oversimplification and the desire for truth. Response to Mermin. Social Studies of
Science 28 (4): 636–40.
Barnes, B. 1999. Biotechnology as expertise. In Nature, risk and responsibility. Discourses of
biotechnology, edited by P. O’Mahony. New York: Routledge.
Barnes, B., David Bloor, and John Henry. 1996. Scientific knowledge: A sociological analysis. Chicago,
IL: The University of Chicago Press.
Bartlett, F. C. 1932. Remembering. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bazzanella, C., and R. Damiano. 1999. The interactional handling of misunderstanding in everyday
conversation. Journal of Pragmatics 31: 817–836.
Bloor, B. 1997. Remember the strong programme? Science, Technology and Human Values 22 (1):
373–85.
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
Social Epistemology 387
Bloor, D. 1999. Anti-Latour. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 30 (1): 81–112.
Blum-Kulka, S., and E. Weizman. 1988. The inevitability of misunderstandings: Discourse
ambiguities. Text 8 (3): 219–41.
Boudon, R. 1994. The art of self-persuasion: The social explanation of false beliefs. Cambridge: Polity
Press.
Boudon. R., and M. Clavelin, eds. 1994. Le relativisme est-il résistible? Regards sur la sociologie des
sciences. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.
Bourdieu, P. 1988. Homo academicus. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bourdieu, P. 2004. Science of science and reflexivity. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Bouvier, A. 1996. La cohérence de l’argumentation philosophique et les normes de la communication. Une perspective de sociologie cognitive. In Descartes et l’argumentation philosophique,
edited by F. Cossutta. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.
Callon, M. 1986. Éléments pour une sociologie de la traduction. La domestication des coquilles
Saint-Jacques et des marins-pêcheurs dans la baie de Saint-Brieuc. L’Année sociologique 36 (1):
169–208.
Carel, M. 1999. Sémantique discursive et sémantique logique: Le cas de mais. Modèles linguistiques
20 (39): 133–44.
Ceccarelli, L. 2001. Shaping science with rhetoric. The cases of Dobzhansky; Schröginger and Wilson.
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Cole, S. 1998. Voodoo sociology: Recent developments in the sociology of science. In The flight from
science and reason, edited by P. R. Gross, N. Levitt, and M. W. Lewis. New York: New York
Academy of Science.
Collins, H. 1985. Changing order. London: Sage.
Collins, H., and T. Pinch. 1979. The Construction of the paranormal: Nothing unscientific is
happening. In On the margins of science: The social construction of rejected science. Social
Review Monograph No. 27, edited by Roy Wallis. Keele, Staffs: Keele University Press.
Collins, H. M. 1981a. Stages for the empirical program of relativism. Social Studies of Science 11 (1):
3–10.
Collins, H. M. 1981b. Son of seven sexes: The social destruction of a physical phenomena. Social
Studies of Science 11 (1): 33–62.
Collins, H. M. 1983. An empirical relativist programme in the sociology of scientific knowledge.
In Science observed, edited by K. Knorr-Cetina and M. Mulkay. London: Sage.
Collins, H. M. 2004. Gravity’s shadow. The search for gravitational waves. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.
Danto, A. C. 1965. Analytical philosophy of history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dascal, M. 1999. Introduction: Some questions about misunderstandings. Journal of Pragmatics 31:
753–762.
Daston, L., ed. 2000. Biographies of scientific objects. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.
Doury, M., and S. Moirand, eds. 2005. L’Argumentation aujourdd’hui. Positions théoriques et
confrontations. Paris: Presses Sorbonne Nouvelle.
Dubois, M. 1998. L’affaire Sokal: Études culturelles et sociologie relativiste des sciences. Revue
française de sociologie 39 (2): 391–418.
Ducrot. O., ed. 1980. Les mots du discours. Paris: Minuit.
Eberlein, G. L. 1994. La nouvelle sociologie des sciences: Un nouvel irrationalisme? In Le relativisme
est-il résistible? Regards sur la sociologie des sciences, edited by R. Boudon and M. Clavelin.
Paris: Presses universitaires de France.
Engelhardt, H., and A. L. Caplan, eds. 1987. Scientific Controversies. Case studies in the resolution and
closure of disputes in science and technologies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Eemeren, F. H. van, and R. Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of argumentation: The pragmadialectic approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Feldman, J. 1999. ‘L’Affaire Sokal’ un épisode de la méconnaissance entre cultures. L’Année
sociologique 49 (2): 245–70.
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
388
Y. Gingras
Fuller, S. 1988. Social epistemology. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Gallie, W. B. 1964. Philosophy and the historical understanding. New York: Schocken Books.
Gingras, Y. 1995. Following scientists through society?—Yes, but at arm’s length! In Scientific
practice. Theories and stories of doing physics, edited by Jed Z. Buchwald. Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press.
Gingras, Y. 1997. The new dialectics of nature. Social Studies of Science 27 (2): 317–24.
Gingras, Y. 1999. From the heights of metaphysics. Social Studies of Science 29 (2): 312–15.
Gingras, Y. 2000. Pourquoi le programme fort est-il incompris? Cahiers internationaux de sociologie
109 (2): 235–55.
Gingras, Y. 2007. Everything you did not necessarily want to know about gravitational waves. And
why. Studies in History and philosophy of Science 38 (1): 269–83.
Gingras, Y., and S. Schweber. 1986, Constraints on construction. Social Studies of Science 16 (2): 372–83.
Godin, B., and Y. Gingras. 2002. The experimeters’ regress: From skepticism to argumentation.
Studies in History and philosophy of Science 33 (1): 137–52.
Gross, A. L. 1996. The rhetoric of science. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Gross, P. R., and Norman Levitt, eds. 1994. Higher superstition. The academic left and its quarrels with
science. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Gross, P. R., N. Levitt, and M. W. Lewis, eds. 1996. The flight from science and reason. New York: New
York Academy of Science.
Hilgartner, S. 1997. The Sokal affair in context. Science, Technology and Human Values 22 (4): 506–22.
Jeanneret, Y. 1998. L’Affaire Sokal ou la querelle des impostures. Paris: Presses universitaires de
France.
Jung, E. H. 2006. Misunderstanding of academic monologues by nonnative speakers of English.
Journal of Pragmatics 38: 1928–1942.
Koertege, N., ed. 1998. A house built on sand: Exploring postmodernist myths about science. New York
& Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Labinger, Jay A., and H. Collins. 2001. The one culture? A conversation about science. Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press.
Lakoff, R. 1971. If’s, and’s, but’s about conjunctions. In Studies in linguistic semantics, edited by
Charles J. Fillmore and D. Terence Langendoen. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Latour, B. 1987. Science in action: How to follow scientists and engineers through society. Milton
Keynes: Open University Press.
Latour, B. 1999. For David Bloor … and beyond: A reply to David Bloor’s “Anti-Latour”. Studies in
History and Philosophy of Science 30 (1): 113–29.
Law, J. 1987. Technology and heterogeneous engineering: The case of Portuguese expansion. In The
social construction of technological systems, edited by W. Bijker, T. Hughes and T. J. Pinch.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Linenthal, E. T., and Tom Engelhardt, eds. 1996. History wars. The Enola Gay and other battles for the
American past. New York: Metropolitan Books.
Lynch, M. 1997. A so-called “fraud”: Moral modulations in a literary scandal. History of the Human
Sciences 10 (3): 9–21.
McLennan, G. 1998. Sociology and cultural studies: Rhetorics of disciplinary identity. History of the
Human Sciences 11 (3): 1–17.
Mermin, N.D. 1998. The science of science. A physicist reads Barnes, Bloor and Henry. Social Studies
of Science 28 (4): 603–29.
Mink, L. O. 1987. Historical understanding. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Nash, G. B., Charlotte Crabtree, and Ross E. Dunn. 1997. History on trial. Culture wars and the
teaching of the past. New York: A. Knopf.
Perelman, C. 1997. L’empire rhétorique. Rhétorique et argumentation. Paris: Vrin.
Perelman, C., and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca. 1988. Traité de l’argumentation, la nouvelle rhétorique.
Bruxelles: Édition de l’Université de Bruxelles
Pickering, A. 1981. The hunting of the quark. Isis 72 (2): 216–36.
Downloaded By: [University of Quebec Montreal] At: 15:50 12 December 2007
Social Epistemology 389
Pickering, A. 1984. Constructing quarks. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.
Pickering, A., ed. 1992. Science as practice and culture. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Pickering, A. 1995. The mangle of practice. Time, agency and science. Chicago, IL: University of
Chicago Press.
Pickering, A. 1999, In the land of the blind … Social Studies of Science 29 (2): 307–11.
Pierssens, M. 1998. Science-en-culture outre-Atlantique. In Impostures scientifiques. Les malentendus
de l’Affaire Sokal, edited by B. Jurdant. Paris: La Découverte.
Pinch, T. 1986. Strata various. Social Studies of Science 16 (4): 705–713.
Ponchon, T. 1993. Le connecteur mais en français moderne. Modèles linquistiques 14 (27): 37–53.
Ricœur, P. 1984. Time and narrative. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Shapin, S. 2001. How to be antiscientific. In The one culture? A conversation about science, edited by
Jay A. Labinger and Harry Collins. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Shapin. S., and S. Schaffer. 1999. Response to Pinnick. Social Studies of Science 29 (2): 250–1.
Tickner, J. A. 1997. You just don’t understand: Troubled engagements between feminists and IR
theorists. International Studies Quarterly 41 (4): 611–32.
Tindale, C.W. 1999. Acts of arguing. A rhetorical model of argument. New York: SUNY.
Tosh, N. 2006. Science, truth and history, Part I. Historiography, relativism and the sociology of
scientific knowledge. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 37 (4): 675–701.
Wacquant, L. 1997. Les dessous de l’Affaire Sokal. II: Petit précis d’alchimie postmoderne. Liber 31:
14–16.
Weigand, E. 1999. Misunderstanding: The standard case. Journal of Pragmatics 31 (6): 763–85.
Zaefferer, D. 1977. Understanding misunderstanding: A proposal for an explanation of reading
choices. Journal of Pragmatics 1 (4): 329–46.