A Freitagian - WordPress.com

Transcription

A Freitagian - WordPress.com
A Freitagian “exploration” of the World-Ecological Crisis:
The Postmodern Ideological-Normative Crisis of the Symbolic
relation to the “monde du vivant”
Martin Samson
Paper presented at the conference, World Society, Planetary Natures: Crisis and Sustainability in the Capitalocene and
Beyond, Binghamton University, July 9-11, 2015. Do not quote without permission
Abstract
When facing the total destruction of the “world of the living” or the “web of life”, and therefore the “nature of
nature” and the “nature of culture” itself, what space is there for normative resistance in postmodern cultural conditions?
This question rooted in Freitag’s “oeuvre” is key in addressing the symbolic dimensions of the ecological crisis in the
postmodern paradigm; both in the development of the crisis and the resistance to globalised neoliberal capitalism. The
answer to this question can hardly be negative, since there can be nothing out of some form of “regulation” in the broad
sense, may it take the shape of modern scientific “laws” which demonstrate “universal regularities” of observable
phenomena, or of normativity and norms which are anchored in the autodetermination of synthetic subjects but which can
be reproduced transformed by them (Freitag in Duclos, 2006: 98-99). Thus, this freitagien perspective will hone in on
two very important interrelated elements. The first being the ideological context, the said space in which the normative
discourse and praxis of resistance can take place and the second being the substance and orientation of this normativity:
both its overt and hidden telos for lack of a better word.
Introduction
When facing the total destruction of the “world of the living” or the “web of life”, and therefore
the “nature of nature” and the “nature of culture” itself, what space is left for normative resistance in
postmodern cultural conditions? This question is rooted in Michel Freitag’s “oeuvre” and is key to
addressing the symbolic dimensions of the ecological crisis in the postmodern paradigm, both in the
development of the crisis and in the resistance to globalized neoliberal capitalism. The answer to this
question can hardly be negative, since nothing can exist outside some form of regulation in the broad
1
sense of the word, be it modern scientific “laws” which demonstrate “universal regularities” of
observable phenomena, or normativity and norms which are anchored in the autodetermination of
synthetic subjects but which can be reproduced after being transformed by them (Freitag in Duclos,
2006: 98-99). Thus, this brief and “bird’s eye view” freitagian exploration of the world-ecology
perspective will hone in on two very important interrelated elements, the first being the ideological
context, the said space in which the normative discourse and praxis of resistance as a socio-ecological
project can exist and the second being the substance and orientation of this normativity – both its
overt and hidden telos for lack of a better word.
In the first part of my presentation I will address Freitag’s concept of the symbolic dimension
of human action, anchored in a concept of the individual subject as a synthetic and reflexive entity. In
the second part, I will do a brief exposé of Freitag’s sociological and philosophical analysis of the
modes of ideological-normative reproduction and regulation of the social order to help us understand
the importance given by Freitag to the concept of Society (with a capital-s) in the production and
reproduction of the ideological-normative landscape. In the third part, I will focus on the modern
roots of the postmodern crisis which emanate from the ideological-normative core of Liberalism. In
the fourth section of my presentation I will address the question of neoliberal capitalism and the
reduction of the symbolic dimension of human action to a systemic auto-referential process “without
subjects or ends”.
1. Michel Freitag’s concept of the symbolic dimension of human action
The second and augmented edition of Michel Freitag’s Introduction générale à une théorie du
symbolique (Introduction to a General Theory of the Symbolic) (Freitag, 2011a) starts with a short
definition of what the author considers as “le symbolique” or “the symbolic”. He states that what he call
in this book the symbolic refers to the whole ontological domain of representation by ideas or
concepts and specifically human life (Freitag, 2011a: 13)1. Not being only an aspect of, but the human
condition itself, the symbolic dimension of human action therefore plays the central role in the
reproduction of a socio-cultural and political order, as the dimension through which meaning is given
and constructed. Thus, for Freitag the making of meaning is inscribed in the dialectics of the symbolic
mediation between actions, norms and meaning in Society. In this sense, and this is an element raised
by many of the author’s students and colleagues (Singer, 2002; Côté & Dagenais, 2002; Bonny, 2002;
Filion, 2006, Dagenais & Gagné, 2014), the individual, society, culture and nature are bound in intricate
dialectical relationships which are neither a priori determined nor undetermined, and which are bound
to socio-historical development and are ultimately an ongoing normative “project”. Hence, we can
state that because of this intricate and “holistic” aspect of the symbolic dimension, it consequently
encompasses the reproduction of an “ecological” order, and thus vital to the world-ecological analysis.
For Freitag, nature and culture, or society are not inscribed in “cartesian duality”2. Although he
addresses both categories neither in the same manner nor as the same reality, the author still
characterises the two as being dialectically linked dimensions of the “monde du vivant” or “world of the
living” (Freitag, 2008). Thus, the concept of Culture and cultures cannot come into being out of the
necessary category of the “living”; in other words, the physiological constitution of human beings as
1
Translation mine.
See Jason Moore (2011a, 2011b) for an in-depth account of the theoretical effect of the Cartesian binary on the
studies of capitalism and ecology.
2
2
sentient beings is the most necessary condition for society. It is in this particular context that, through
sensory-motor, symbolic and formal-operational mediations, humans can construct cultural and
symbolic orders. Reality as a totality is then conferred meaning though multiple symbolic prisms or
lenses3.
One could easily interpret Freitag’s thought as an anthropocentric one, which would not be a
completely false interpretation. However, this position, with all its ethical implications, comes from
specific epistemological and normative choices. First, the current ecological crisis is caused by humans
and capitalism, therefore by the Anthropos itself and its creation. Freitag would reject attempts to take
capitalism as a-historical, or out-of-society; he thus integrates it into the realm of human action.
Second, Freitag is very critical of biocentric an antihumanist approaches (Freitag, 2002a, 2002b, 2006,
2008; Lafontaine, 2004) to the ecological crisis because they are generally submitted to the “cybernetic
paradigm” (Weiner, 1954 in Lafontaine, 2004) or system-centered (Luhman, 2012) analyses. These
analyses become normative dead-ends by reducing “human action” to “the agency of the actor”, and
by separating the “actors” from the systems. Furthermore, they separate the said systems from the
socio-political and normative dimension of responsibility. Finally these analyses separate the human
reality from extra-human nature, and thus by expulsing the human from the biosphere, they tend
either to normatively put the latter over the former, or relativize the place of human activity in the
world of the living which creates new modes of “belief” which could justify authoritative modes of
societal regulation by legitimizing eco-technocratic as seen in The Imperative of Responsibility of
Hans Jonas (1985), and other radical conservationist measures, found in authors such as Holmes
Rolston III (Siurua, 2006) and proponents of deep ecology (Pepper, 1993; Lafontaine, 2004).
Consequently, the “world of the living” does not appear to itself by itself, but through a specific
symbolic order (Freitag, 2008: 392) through which it is given meaning. Since this symbolic order is
fundamentally linked to the ideological and normative social conditions, it therefore skews, and orients
the individual’s and society’s said relation to the world. This pushes the need to look at the specific
social and societal contexts in which these conditions take shape and are reproduced.
2 The socio-historical mutation of the ideological-normative landscape
In his work, Freitag’s analysis of sociohistorical transformation was not one of capitalism per
se. His main focus was the relationship between the cultural, symbolic and political orders in which
the ideological-normative fabric of society was produced and reproduced. Following the sociological
tradition of “ideal-types”, Michel Freitag developed a general theory of society in which he identifies
three general types of western societies: the pre-modern or cultural-symbolic society, the modern or
political-institutional society, and the postmodern or operational-decisional society. In a perspective
of the “longue durée”, society changes through, and is marked by, mutations and transitions which
relate to the legitimization of its ideological-normative order. For example, the transition from premodern to modern society was one of gradual and radical scissions in the mode of reproduction
3
On this subject, Freitag has also developed a position on the rupture and continuity between humans and animals
which was influenced by zoologist Adolf Portmann. For further discussions on the subject see Freitag (2002c;
Freitag in Duclos, 2006) and the article « La société informatique et le respect des formes » in Freitag (1998a).
3
through a cultural-symbolic one characterised4 by the inherent legitimacy of tradition (Freitag, 1989,
1998, 1999, 2002). In traditional societies, authority imposes norms on social relations as part of a
“jurisdictional deduction based on the privileges and power, or capacity to act, conducive to different
social groups, and which manifest themselves together in the necessary order of society” (Gagné,
1991: 28)5. Authority therefore acquires its legitimacy in respecting this order. Therefore, the process
of institutionalization the authority goes through is always linked to the preservation of tradition and
to the processes of reconstructing harmony through social change (Freitag, 1989; Gagné 1992).
It is again through a long-term process that, this “first” mode lost its legitimacy considering its
inherent conflict with the process of individualism and the abstraction of the source of the ideologicalnormative fabric of society, or what Freitag calls the process of “radical transcendentalization of the
subject”. Indeed, the “embedded” sense-making dimension of everyday practices went through a
process of abstraction and became dissociated from the embedded and lived community and thus was
reoriented towards an overarching “source” of normativity (1989, 1999). Through this process, the
ideological-normative dimension came less from the ecological relation between the community and
the living world, from its traditions or cultures, than from an otherworldly authority.
Metaphorically, this could be the transformation from the pre-modern anthropological
conceptualization of the “being-of-this-world”, in which humans and thus society emanates from the
world of the living, to the monotheistic “being-in-the-world”, wherein humans are “put” in the
empirical world of the living or the “down here” but do not belong to it, belonging instead to “the
beyond” (Freitag in Duclos, 2006: 102). The process of abstraction will take its most notable turn in
the political-institutional mode which is characterized by the replacement of tradition with
transcendental Reason, as the means of legitimizing the normative fabric of a society, in which a
deliberative institutional space shaped by relations of domination, in Weberian terms, “democratizes”
the reproduction of the said society. This movement of abstraction is dialectically linked to the
production of the concept of the individual and its emancipation from the socio-ecological conditions
of the world and the production of transcendental Reason (Freitag, 1998).
However, this abstraction also took place in a specific context: the development of primitive
forms of accumulation of capital (Harvey, 2003, 2005) growingly in opposition with the culturalsymbolic regulation, thus fueling the emancipation away from traditional and cultural normativity. In
this sense, one could see capitalism as a mode of production born out of which was initially a process
autonomy, and tends to further this autonomy, by breaking away from cultural or political regulation
(Freitag, 1998, 2002, 2008). In Freitagian terms, throughout the political-institutional mode of social
reproduction of modernity, capitalism was in constant opposition with socio-ecologically embedded
regulation and thus its own embedding into a normative framework. Consequently, it seems important
to state that Michel Freitag often refers to the distinction between oikonomia (economics) and
chrematistics (Freitag, 2002, 2006, 2008) and therefore adheres largely to Aristotle’s depiction of the
pre-modern socio-culturally regulated oikonomia and to his critique of chrematistics which was
associated to the “metoikos”, the meta-oikos, or the one who is out of the culturally-embedded
regulation of the City, therefore not regulated by the norms of the city, i.e. the outsider.
4
It should be noted that this ideal type is exposed here in its most generalized concept. This mode spans a long
period of time and is consequently comprised of many different empirical and sociopolitical iterations. A more indepth assessment of the process of “longue durée” can be found in Freitag (1989).
5
Translation mine.
4
Throughout the development of his theory of society, Freitag focus largely on capitalism,
without finding fault with it. One could argue then that his critique of capitalism is a critique of the
reproduction of the capitalistic order of society which takes place in the modes of social and societal
reproduction. In fact, the author sees mainly Liberalism as the fundamental normative milestone of
the reproduction of the capitalistic society. It is through the concept of “natural individual rights”,
based in Reason and taken as a new ideological-normative foundation external to a collective or
culturally-related concept of tradition, that the double normative core of modernity and Liberal
modernity will be crucial to understand the symbolic dimension of postmodern neoliberal capitalism.
3 The modern roots of the postmodern crisis and the ideological-normative core of Liberalism
Consequently, the current postmodern cultural conditions and the “crisis of the symbolic” to
which they are associated in Freitag’s work are the result of socio-ecological mutations which have
affected the political-institutional mode of societal reproduction associated to modernity. These
mutations were already in “potentiality” in the two socio-cultural conditions forming the basis upon
which practical, or ethical and normative, reason could flourish in Liberal modernity. I am referring
to the production of the double ideological-normative core of modernity crystallized through
Liberalism: the negative ontological principle of individual liberty and the positive principle of the
natural inclination towards passions6.
The first principle legitimized the emancipation and liberation from tradition. In this sense, the
concept of the freedom of individuals is, in its own logic, incompatible with any kind of absolutism
coming from an illegitimate source (Freitag, 1998 in Samson, 2015: 7). The second principle made it
possible to establish a positive social order based on the acceptance of certain realities which could be
deemed “common” and to raise a transcendental political “Reason” to be raised above particular
“reasons” through institutionalization. Therefore it allowed a socio-political entity, which would be
“Society” (with a capital-s) as a conceptual category, or a civilization, to strive for a particular social or
common good. The latter principle can therefore be seen as a safeguard from the excesses of the
former, by being the very foundation of the political, reflexive and deliberative space in which to
debate the question of the common good.
However, Freitag insists on the fact that these two distinctively “modern” philosophical
principles have been woven into capitalism rather quickly if not from the start, highlighting the
difficulty to determine exactly where the difference between “liberalism” and “liberal capitalism”
(Freitag, 2008). However, it is clear that this particular socio-historical development cannot be
considered apart from the hegemonic position of the Anglo-Saxon Enlightenment, characterised by
empiricism as epistemology, utilitarianism as ethics and pragmatism as political action, in the
construction of the ideological and normative fabric of the western world’s capitalistic social imaginary
(Freitag, 1998: 214).
Therefore capitalism emanates both ideologically and normatively from the symbolic
interrelation between individuals, society and the world of through a “movement” of liberation from
political-cultural constraints to both individuals and the general realm of human action. In this sense,
Freitag asserts how “capitalism was consequentially born from the radical liberation of modern
6
See a more detailed account of this dimension of Freitag’s theory (1987, 1988a, 1988b, 1996a, 1998, 2002a,
2011).
5
individualism with regards to freedom and reason; and its development therefore coincides with the
reduction of the Enlightenment’s transcendental Reason to utility, and from utility to profit.” (Freitag,
2008: 12)7. The author again refers to this aspect as the distinction between the normative dimensions
of the socio-culturally, if not ecologically-embedded oikonomia and the systemic pragmatic
chrematistics. Although one can easily see the normative and very “Polanyi-like” distinction between
embedded and disembedded modes of regulation, it should be noted that the disembedded or
autonomous mode of regulation is also inscribed in a particular normative framework, and is therefore
not a-normative. In other words there is nothing out of the normative, in the realm of human action.
4 Neoliberal capitalism and the reduction of the symbolic dimension of human action to a systemic
auto-referential process “without subjects or ends”
At the core of Michel Freitag’s critique of postmodernity we find the dialectical relationship
between the capitalist mode of production, the principle of negative liberty and the natural inclination
towards passions which has produced and reproduce the legitimacy of the societal order through a
process of fragmentation and dissolution of society as a concrete and synthetic totality (Freitag, 1998a,
2002a). In l’Abîme de la liberté (Freitag, 2011c), which could be translated as the “the abyss of freedom”,
a posthumous book, Freitag hones in on the contemporary socio-ecological condition of individual
freedom through its complex evolution in both liberal and neoliberal empirical, utilitarian and
pragmatic paradigm.
The birth of modern empirical social sciences became the theoretical, conceptual and
pedagogical space which could contribute to the political legitimization of social order. However, these
social sciences took root in the ideological-normative domination of the Anglo-Saxon Enlightenment
in which empirical, utilitarian and pragmatism shaped the very conditions in which the symbolic, or
meaning-making dimension, was confined to individual spirituality and religions on the one hand, and
which reduced questions of meaning and the common good to cost-benefit calculations. In fact, this
is the starting point for both the principle of negative liberty and the natural inclination towards
passions becoming the contemporary norm. In this sense, modern economic liberalism was aimed at
liberating individuals from the weight of irrational norms and despotic configuration of power and
authority, which was the basis of the idea of Progress (Freitag, 2006; Freitag, 2008: 23). But at the
same time, this very concept of “Progress” was being laid against the nominalist position of positive
sciences which put in questionned the idea of a “transcendental” or “universal” progress and restricted
the idea of “truth” and knowledge to pure empiricism, and also the ideological-normative structure of
capitalism in which the idea of progress had been transformed into that of development (Freitag, 1998,
2006, 2008).
In the neoliberal age, development as the generally accepted form of progress and freedom
appear related very differently than during modernity. Through the radical process of “freedom from”
socio-ecological normativity resulting from negative liberty and the natural inclination towards
passions, neoliberal capitalism produces a concept of freedom very different from the on of its modern
iteration. It transforms the subject of freedom itself and anchors it in a different sphere of normativity.
Hence, the ideological-normative and expressive substance of the individual’s inherent freedom, as a
“fundamental human right” or an emancipatory political end, is semantically transformed, into a dual
concept of freedom. As suggested by Alain Bihr (2007: 133), neoliberal capitalism, on the one hand,
7
Translation mine.
6
promotes the conceptualization of individual freedom that completely negates the very concept of a
“collective freedom”, thus creating what one could call radical individualism, and on the other,
reorients the very subject of freedom, from the “human-as-individual” to the “organisation-asindividual”.
Freitag also argues that the neoliberal metaphysical doctrine of the “freedom of the individual”
takes shape in a context in which the totality of life is dominated by corporations and organisations,
reducing the ideal of the individual to a trivial marketing ploy in order to shape and justify the systemic
auto-referential logic of capital (Freitag, 2008: 23). Hence, the need to outline the fact that both “ideas
of freedom” demand different sphere of normativity. The first could be framed normatively in the
fundamental moral and political concept of emancipation, and the second in the “apolitical” and autoregulated processes of the market laws. According to neoliberalism, the normative dimension of the
market is naturalized as market rules and as being an empirical fact, as scientific and, as mentioned at
the beginning, as demonstrating “universal regularities” of observable phenomena. The concept of
freedom becomes a “rule” devoid of any basis in the individual’s subjective dimension. Thus the
concept of neoliberal freedom is a freedom for “freedom’s sake” (Freitag, 199a, 2006, 2008: 22-23;
Freitag in Duclos, 2006: 116) and is conceptualized as being a cardinal principle of a systemic
environment separated from the very socio-ecological conditions in which human activity emerges
and takes shape.8
Conclusion
Neoliberal ideology has shaped the normative landscape in a way that both the political “right”
and “left” have become two sides of the same coin. It is completely integrated into the operationaldecisional and systemic mode of societal reproduction, meaning that the political-institutional mode
present in modernity, while still present has gone through a substantial transformation on the basis of
its normative grounds. Though being ever-present and dominant, the “action” of the State has been
fully integrated in hegemonic neoliberal ideologico-normative structures. With the dissolution of the
welfare or social State, we can see the definite political consecration of the already hegemonic position
of neoliberalism in the field of economics, of scientific research, social rights, all levels of education
from, kindergarten to university which strengthen the systemic end of “adaptation” to the
development and expansion of capitalism. Furthermore, this ideological, normative, political and
social “dialectic” strengthens the reproduction of the idea that the symbolic dimension of human
activity is reduced to information and communication, and that the fundamental socio-ecological
anchoring of human action is therefore reduced to producing and reproducing the neoliberal status quo
and adapting to its ever-changing and growing need to push back the socio-ecological normative limits
of the auto-referential regulation of systemic global capitalism (Freitag, 2002, 2008).
When facing the total destruction of the “world of the living” or the “web of life”, and therefore
the “nature of nature” and the “nature of culture” itself, what space is left for normative resistance in
postmodern cultural conditions? The space is one of radical change, where “conserving” the
conditions in which the dialectical “nature of nature” and the “nature of culture” are intertwined, and
which shapes itself though the repossession of the means of producing the symbolic order in which
the “mondialisation” opposes the “globalisation”, or where “worldalization” or the creation of an
intercivisational oikoumené (Freitag, 2008, 2011c) must be the way to foster the reproduction of human
8
For an interesting contrast to this concept of freedom, but with similar conclusions, see Bihr (2007).
7
symbolic orders against the general conformism of postmodern neoliberal capitalism (Castoriadis,
1992, 1996).
8
Bibliography
Bihr, A., La novlangue néolibérale, (Lausanne : Page Deux, 2007).
Castoriadis, C., L'Institution imaginaire de la société, (Paris : Seuil : 1975)
_____, Les Carrefours du labyrinthe II : Domaines de l'homme, (Paris : Seuil, 1986)
_____, Les carrefours du labyrinthe III : Le Monde morcelé, (Paris : Seuil, 1990)
_____, (1992), « The retreat from autonomy: Post-Modernism as Generalized Conformism » dans
Thesis Eleven, February 31, pp.14-23.
_____, Les Carrefours du labyrinthe IV - La Montée de l'insignifiance, (Paris : Seuil, 1996)
Côté, J.-F., Dagenais, D., (2002), “ Dialectical Sociology in Québec: About and around Michel
Freitag's "Dialectique et Société"” in The American Sociologist, Vol. 33, No. 2 Summer, pp. 4056
Dagenais, D. (dir.), Hannah Arendt, le totalitarisme et le monde contemporain, (Québec : PUL, 2003).
Dagenais, D., Gagné, G., (dirs), La sociologie de Michel Freitag, (Montréal : Nota Bene, 2014).
Duclos, D., (dir.), Pourquoi tardons-nous tant à devenir écologistes? Limites de la postmodernité et société écologique,
(Paris : L’Harmattan, 2006).
Durkheim, É., De la division du travail social, huitième édition, (Paris : PUF, 1967).
_____, (1889), « Communauté et société selon Tönnies. » Une édition électronique réalisée à partir
de la Revue philosophique, 27, 1889, pp. 416 à 422. Les Classiques des sciences sociales de
l’UQAC consulté le 29 juin 2014 sur :
http://classiques.uqac.ca/classiques/Durkheim_emile/textes_1/textes_1_13/communaute_
societe_tonnies.pdf
Dumont, L., Essai sur l’individualisme. Une perspective anthropologique sur l’idéologie moderne, (Paris : Seuil
[Points Essais], 1983).
Filion, J.-F., Sociologie dialectique : introduction à l’œuvre de Michel Freitag, (Québec : Nota Bene, 2006).
Freitag, M., Dialectique et société. Tome I : Introduction à une théorie générale du Symbolique, (Montréal : Éditions
coopératives Albert Saint-Martin, 1986a).
_____, Dialectique et société. Tome II : Culture, pouvoir, contrôle. Les modes de reproduction formels de la société,
(Montréal : Éditions coopératives Albert Saint-Martin, 1986b).
_____, (1987), « Les sciences sociales contemporaines et le problème de la normativité », revue Sociologie
et sociétés, vol. XIX, no 2 octobre, pp. 15-35.
_____, (1988a), « Éclatement du social ou oubli de la société », Société, 3 : 9-25
9
_____, (1988b) : « La raison contre les raisons », Société, 2, pp. 181-230.
_____, (1989), « La genèse du politique dans les sociétés traditionnelles. I. De la communauté tribale
à la royauté », Société, 6, pp. 41-122.
_____, (1994), « La métamorphose, Genèse et développement d’une société postmoderne en
Amérique », dans Société, no05, 12-13 hiver, pp. 1-137)
_____, (1996a), « Le dilemme des sciences sociales dans la postmodernité : étudier et orienter la
société, ou produire le social ? », dans RAFIE, M., (dir.), Les sciences humaines, état des lieux,
Québec, Les Presses de l’Université Laval, p. 29-66.
_____, (1996b), « L’hypocrisie épistémologique des sciences sociales : construction critique de l’objet
sociologique ou production technocratique du social », dans De la conception du social à la
construction de l’objet sociologique, Actes du 3eColloque étudiant interuniversitaire de sociologie,
Québec, Les Presses de l’Université Laval, p. 1-22.
_____, Le naufrage de l’université et autres essais d’épistémologie politique, 2e édition (Québec : Nota Bene,
1998a).
_____, (1998b), « Pour une approche théorique de la postmodernité comprise comme une mutation
de la société », in Société no 18-19 été, p. 1-61.
_____, (1999), « La dissolution postmoderne de la référence transcendantale : perspectives
théoriques », Cahiers de recherche sociologique, Montréal, 33, pp. 181-217.
_____, L’oubli de la société. Pour une théorie critique de la postmodernité, (Québec : PUL, 2002a).
_____, (2002b), « De la terreur nazie au meilleur des mondes cybernétiques. Réflexions sociologiques
sur les tendances totalitaires de notre époque. » in Arguments, vol. 5 no. 1 Automne - Hiver,
consulted [online] <http://www.revueargument.ca/article/2002-10-01/214-de-la-terreurnazie-au-meilleur-des-mondes-cybernetique.html>, April 4th, 2014.
_____, (2002c), « Actualité de l’animal, virtualité de l’homme ». Entrevue avec Michel Freitag. Propos
recueillis par le Collectif Société, in Conjonctures, no 33-34, automne 2001 – hiver 2002, pp.
99-154.
_____, (2003), « De la terreur nazie au meilleur des mondes cybernétique. Réflexion sociologique sur
la tendance totalitaire de notre époque », Argument, automne-hiver, 5, 1, pp. 74-98.
_____, (2004), « Réponses au questionnaire du GÉODE », dans Alain CAILLÉ (dir.), Une théorie
sociologique générale est-elle pensable ?, Revue du MAUSS, pp. 255-267.
_____, (2006), “ Combien de temps le développement peut-il encore durer ?” Les ateliers de l’éthique, la
revue du CRÉUM, vol. 1, no 2, automne/hiver 2006, pp. 114-133.
_____, L’impasse de la globalisation, Propos recueillis par Patrick Ernst, (Montréal, Écosociété : 2008).
10
_____, Dialectique et société, vol. 1. La connaissance sociologique, (Montréal, Liber, 2011a).
_____, Dialectique et société, vol. 2. Introduction à une théorie générale du symbolique, (Montréal, Liber, 2011b).
_____, L'abîme de la liberté. Critique du libéralisme, (Montréal, Liber, 2011c).
_____, Dialectique et société, vol. 3. Culture, pouvoir, contrôle, (Montréal, Liber, 2013).
Freitag, M., Pineault, É., (dirs), Le monde enchaîné. Perspective sur l’AMI et sur le capitalisme globalisé,
(Québec : Nota bene, 1999a)
Gagné, G., (1992), « Les transformations du droit dans la problématique de la transition à la
postmodernité » in Belley, J.-G., Issalys, P., Aux frontières du juridique. Études interdisciplinaires
sur les transformations du droit, (Québec : GEPTUD, 1993).
Jonas, H. The imperative of responsibility, (Chicago (IL): University of Chicago Press, 1985).
Singer, B., (2002), “Introduction to Freitag” in European Journal of Social Theory 5(2): 171–173
Vibert, S. « La référence à la société comme « totalité », Pour un réalisme ontologique de l’être-ensociété. (Sociologie dialectique et anthropologie holiste) », Revue du MAUSS permanente, 19 juin
2007 [consulté en ligne le 15 septembre 2014] : http://www.journaldumauss.net/./?Lareference-a-la-societe-comme
11